[Thatcher Introduction]: Marcus Tullius
Sulla's constitution had been gradually changing since his death, and
Cicero slowly came to side with the optimates as against the populares and to
try to carry the equestrians with him. He might have been a member of the
"First Triumvirate" but perhaps preferred the existing institutions
to such high-handed measures. In 58 B.C. he was exiled through the efforts of
the demagogue Publius Clodius, but was recalled the next year. When civil war
broke out between Caesar and Pompey,
On the Laws:
Book II
4. Marcus: Let us, then, once more examine, before we come to
the consideration of particular laws, what is the power and nature of law in
general; lest, when we come to refer everything to it, we occasionally make
mistakes from the employment of incorrect language, and show ourselves ignorant
of the force of those terms which we ought to employ in the definition of laws.
Quintus: This is a very necessary caution, and the proper method of
seeking truth.
Marcus: This, then, as it appears to me, has been the decision of the
wisest philosophers---that law was neither a thing to be contrived by the
genius of man, nor established by any decree of the people, but a certain
eternal principle, which governs the entire universe, wisely commanding what is
right and prohibiting what is wrong. Therefore, they called that aboriginal and
supreme law the mind of God, enjoining or forbidding each separate thing in
accordance with reason. On which account it is that this law, which the gods
have bestowed upon the human race, is so justly applauded. For it is the reason
and mind of a wise Being equally able to urge us to good or to deter us from
evil.
Quintus: You have, on more than one occasion, already touched on this
topic. But before you come to treat of the laws of nations, I wish you would
endeavor to explain the force and power of this divine and celestial law, lest
the torrent of custom should overwhelm our understanding, and betray us into
the vulgar method of expression.
Marcus: From our childhood we have learned, my Quintus, to call such
phrases as this "that a man appeals to justice, and goes to law," and
many similar expressions "law," but, nevertheless, we should
understand that these, and other similar commandments and prohibitions, have
sufficient power to lead us on to virtuous actions and to call us away from
vicious ones. Which power is not only far more ancient than any existence of
states and people, but is coeval with God himself, who beholds and governs both
heaven and earth. For it is impossible that the divine mind can exist in a
state devoid of reason; and divine reason must necessarily be possessed of a
power to determine what is virtuous and what is vicious. Nor, because it was
nowhere written, that one man should maintain the pass of a bridge against the
enemy's whole army, and that he should order the bridge behind him to be cut
down, are we therefore to imagine that the valiant Cocles [i.e., Horatius]
did not perform this great exploit agreeably to the laws of nature and the
dictates of true bravery. Again, though in the reign of Tarquin there was no
written law concerning adultery, it does not therefore follow that Sextus
Tarquinius did not offend against the eternal law when he committed a rape on
Lucretia, daughter of Tricipitius. For, even then he had the light of reason
from the nature of things, that incites to good actions and dissuades from evil
ones; and which does not begin for the first time to be a law when it is drawn
up in writing, but from the first moment that it exists. And this existence of
moral obligation is co-eternal with that of the divine mind. Therefore, the
true and supreme law, whose commands and prohibitions are equally
authoritative, is the right reason of the Sovereign Jupiter.
5. Quintus: I grant you, my brother, that whatever is just is
also at all times the true law; nor can this true law either be originated or
abrogated by the written forms in which decrees are drawn up.
Marcus: Therefore, as that Divine Mind, or reason, is the
supreme law, so it exists in the mind of the sage, so far as it can be
perfected in man. But with respect to civil laws, which are drawn up in various
forms, and framed to meet the occasional requirements of the people, the name
of law belongs to them not so much by right as by the favor of the people. For
men prove by some such arguments as the following, that every law which
deserves the name of a law, ought to be morally good and laudable. It is clear,
say they, that laws were originally made for the security of the people, for
the preservation of states, for the peace and happiness of society; and that
they who first framed enactments of that kind, persuaded the people that they
would write and publish such laws only as should conduce to the general
morality and happiness, if they would receive and obey them. And then such
regulations, being thus settled and sanctioned, they justly entitled Laws. From
which we may reasonably conclude, that those who made unjustifiable and
pernicious enactments for the people, acted in a manner contrary to their own
promises and professions, and established anything rather than laws, properly
so called, since it is evident that the very signification of the word
"law" comprehends the whole essence and energy of justice and equity.
I would, therefore, interrogate you on this point, my Quintus, as those
philosophers are in the habit of doing. If a state wants something for the want
of which it is reckoned no state at all, must not that something be something
good?
Quintus: A very great good.
Marcus: And if a state has no law, is it not for that reason to be
reckoned no state at all?
Quintus: We must needs say so.
Marcus: We must therefore reckon law among the very best things.
Quintus: I entirely agree with you.
Marcus: If, then, in the majority of nations, many pernicious and
mischievous enactments are made, which have no more right to the name of law
than the mutual engagement of robbers, are we bound to call them laws? For as
we cannot call the recipes of ignorant and unskillful empirics, who give
poisons instead of medicines, the prescriptions of a physician, so likewise we
cannot call that the true law of a people, of whatever kind it may be, if it
enjoins what is injurious, let the people receive it as they will. For law is
the just distinction between right and wrong, made conformable to that most
ancient nature of all, the original and principal regulator of all things, by
which the laws of men should be measured, whether they punish the guilty or
protect and preserve the innocent.
6. Quintus: I quite understand you, and think that no law but
that of justice should either be proclaimed as one or enforced as one.
Marcus: Then you regard as null and void the laws of Titius and
Apuleius, because they are unjust.
Quintus: Yes; and I would say the same of the laws of Livius.
Marcus: You are right, and so much more the more, since a single vote
of the senate would be sufficient to abrogate them in an instant. But that law
of justice, the power of which I have explained, can never be abrogated.
Certainly, if I could get you both to agree with me. But Plato, that wisest of
all men, that most dignified of all philosophers, who was the first man who
ever composed a treatise on a Commonwealth, and afterwards a separate one on
Laws, induces me to follow his illustrious example, and to proclaim the praises
of law, before I begin to recite its regulations. Such, likewise, was the
practice of Zaleucus and Charondas, who wrote the laws which they gave their
cities, not for the sake of study or amusement, but for the benefit of their
country and their fellow-citizens. And imitating them, Plato considered that it
was the property of law, to persuade in some instances, and not to compel
everything by threats and violence.
Quintus: What, do you venture to cite Zaleucus, when Timaeus denies
that he ever existed ?
Marcus: But Theophrastus, an author, in my opinion, quite as
respectable, and as may think, much more so, corroborates my statement. His
fellow-citizens, too, my clients, the Locrians, commemorate him; but whether he
was a real man or not, is of no great consequence to our argument; we are only
speaking according to tradition.
7. Let this, therefore, be a fundamental principle in all societies,
that the gods are the supreme lords and governors of all things---that all
events are directed by their influence, and wisdom, and Divine power; that they
deserve very well of the race of mankind; and that they likewise know what sort
of person every one really is; that they observe his actions, whether good or
bad; that they take notice with what feelings and with what piety he attends to
his religious duties, and that they are sure to make a difference between the
good and the wicked.
For when once our minds are confirmed in these views, it will not be
difficult to inspire them with true and useful sentiments. For what can be more
true than that no man should be so madly presumptuous as to believe that he has
either reason or intelligence, while he does not believe that the heaven and
the world possess them likewise, or to think that those things which he can
scarcely comprehend by the greatest possible exertion of his intellect, are put
in motion without the agency of reason?
In truth, we can scarcely reckon him a man, whom neither the regular courses
of the stars, nor the alterations of day and night, nor the temperature of the seasons,
nor the productions that nature displays for his use and enjoyment, urge to
gratitude towards heaven.
And as those beings which are furnished with reason are incomparably
superior to those which want it, and as we cannot say, without impiety, that
anything is superior to the universal Nature, we must therefore confess that
divine reason is contained within her. And who will dispute the utility of
these sentiments, when he reflects how many cases of the greatest importance
are decided by oaths; how much the sacred rites performed in making treaties
tend to assure peace and tranquility; and what numbers of people the fear of
divine punishment has reclaimed from a vicious course of life; and how sacred
the social rights must be in a society where a firm persuasion obtains the
immediate intervention of the immortal gods, both as witnesses and judges of
our actions? Such is the "preamble of the law," to use the expression
of Plato.
Quintus: I understand you, my brother; and I am greatly pleased to
find that you take a different view of the subject, and dwell upon other points
of it, than those which he selects, for nothing can less resemble his opinions,
than what you have just now asserted, even in this preamble. The only matter in
which you seem to me to imitate him, is his style and language.
Marcus: I wish, indeed, I did, but who is, or who ever will be able
to translate them, and, indeed, that is what I should do if I did not wish to
be altogether original. For what difficulty is there in stating the same
doctrines as he does, translated from him almost word for word?
Quintus: I entirely agree with you; for as you have just remarked,
your arguments ought to be entirely your own. Begin, then, if you will do us a
favor, and expound the laws of religion.
Marcus: I will explain them as well as I can; and since both the
topic and the conversation is a familiar one, I shall begin by describing the
laws of laws.
Quintus: What laws do you mean?
Marcus: There are certain terms in law, my Quintus, not so ancient as
those in the primitive sacred laws, but still, in order to carry with them
greater authority, being of a somewhat greater antiquity than the common
parlance of people. These legal terms, I shall mention with as much brevity as
possible; and I shall endeavor to expound the laws, not, indeed, in their whole
extent, for this would be a boundless subject, but those which involve the
principles, and contain the sum and substance of the rest.
Quintus: This appears a most desirable method; let us therefore hear
the terms of the law.
8. Quintus: Such are the following:---Let men approach the
gods with purity---let men appear before them in the spirit of devotion---let
men remove riches from their temples; whoever does otherwise shall suffer the
vengeance of heaven---let no one have private gods---neither new gods nor
strange gods, unless publicly acknowledged, are to be worshiped privately---let
the temples which our fathers have constructed in the cities, be upheld---let
the people maintain the groves in the country, and the abodes of the Lares---let
men preserve the customs of their fathers and of their family---let the gods
who have been accounted celestial be worshiped, and those likewise who have
merited celestial honors by their illustrious actions, such as Hercules,
Bacchus, Aesculapius, Castor, Pollux, and Quirinus. Let due honor be likewise
paid to those virtues, by which man is exalted to heaven---as Intelligence,
Valor, Piety, Fidelity; and let temples be consecrated to their honor---with
regard to the vices, let no sacred sacrifices be paid to them.
Let men put aside all contentions of every kind on the sacred festivals, and
let servants enjoy them, their toils being remitted, for therefore they were
appointed at certain seasons.---Let the priests duly render the public
thank-offerings to heaven, with herbs and fruits, on the sacrificial days.
Also, on the appointed holidays, let them offer up the cream of milk, and the
sucklings; and lest the priests should commit any mistakes in these sacrifices,
or the season of these sacrifices, let them carefully observe the calendar, and
the revolutions of the stars.---Let them provide those particular victims which
are most appropriate and agreeable to each particular deity.---Let the
different gods have different orders of priests.---Let them all have pontiffs
in common; and let each separate god have his Flamen.
Let the Vestal Virgins in the city carefully keep the eternal fire of the
public altar always burning; and, that this may be done both publicly and
privately with all due form and ceremony, let those who are not instructed in
the order of the ceremonials learn it from the public priests. Let there be two
classes of these priests, one to preside over ceremonials and sacrifices, and
the other to interpret the obscure predictions of the prophets and diviners,
whenever the senate and the people require it. Let the public Augurs, who are
the interpreters of the all-good and all-great Jupiter, likewise examine the
presages and the auspices, according to the discipline of their art. Let the
priests who are conversant in auguries implore prosperity for the vineyards and
gardens, and pray for the general welfare of the people. Let those who give
counsel in military or civic affairs attend to the auspices, and be guided by
them. Let them guard against the anger of heaven, and appease it; and observe
from what part of heaven the lightnings burst forth. Let them declare what
lands, cities, and temples, are to be held free and consecrated. Whatever
things the augur declares to be unjust, ill-omened, vicious, and accursed, let
them be forsaken as prohibited and disastrous, and whoever will not obey these
divine indications, let him suffer capital punishment.
9. As to alliances, peace, war, truces, and the rights of ambassadors,
let the two Fetiales be the appropriate judges, and let them determine
all questions relating to military affairs. Let them report all prodigies and
portents to the Etruscans and soothsayers, if the senate orders it; and let the
chiefs of Etruria explain their system. Then will they learn what deities it
behooves them to propitiate, and deprecate the fury of the thunderbolt against
the object of its vengeance.
Let there be no nocturnal sacrifices performed by women, except those which
they offer according to custom on behalf of the people; and let none be
initiated in the mysteries except by the usual forms consecrated to Ceres,
according to the Grecian ceremonials.
A crime which has been committed and cannot be expiated has been an act of
impiety; as to the faults which can be expiated, let the public priests expiate
them.
Let men temper the public hilarity with song, and harp, and flute at the
public games, as far as can be done without the games of the racecourse and the
wrestling-matches, and let them unite these amusements with the honors of the
gods. Let them retain whatever is best and purest in the ancient form of
worship. Except the devotees of Cybele, to whom this privilege is allowed on
certain days, let no one presume to levy rates for private emolument. Whoever
purloins or robs any temple, or steals any property deposited in a temple,
shall be accounted a parricide. The divine punishment of perjury is
destruction---the human penalty is infamy. With regard to incest, let the chief
priest sentence it to the extreme penalty of the law.
Let not the impious man attempt to appease the gods by gifts and offerings.
Let vows be carefully performed. Wherever law is violated let its punishments
be executed. Let no private person presume to consecrate his land; and let his
consecration of gold, silver, and ivory, be made within the limits of
moderation. Let the sacred actions of private persons be preserved for ever.
Let the rights of the deities of the dead be considered sacred. Let those who have
passed into the world of souls be considered as deified! but let men diminish
the unnecessary expense and sorrow which is lavished on them.
10. Atticus: You have managed to include a great deal of law
in a very small compass; but it seems to me, that this class of religious
maxims does not much differ from the Laws of Numa and our national
regulations.
Marcus: Do you suppose, then, that when, in my Treatise on the
Commonwealth, Scipio appears to be arguing that our ancient Roman
Commonwealth was the best of all republics, it was not indispensable that I
should give laws of corresponding excellence to that best of all republics?
Atticus: Undoubtedly I think you should.
Marcus: Well, then, you may expect such laws as may embrace that most
perfect kind of republic. And if any others should haply be demanded of me this
day, which are not to be found, and never have existed, in our Roman
Commonwealth, yet even these formed a portion of the customs of our ancestors,
which at that time were maintained as religiously as the laws themselves.
Book III.
1. Marcus: I shall, therefore, imitate that divine man, who
has inspired me with such admiration that I eulogize him perhaps oftener than
is necessary.
Atticus: You mean Plato.
Marcus: The very man, my Atticus.
Atticus: Indeed you do not exaggerate your compliments, nor bestow
them too frequently, for even my Epicurean friends, who do not like any one to
be praised but their own master, still allow me to love Plato as much as I
like.
Marcus: They do well to grant you this indulgence, for what can be so
suitable to the elegance of your taste as the writings of Plato, who in his
life and manners appears to me to have succeeded in that most difficult
combination of gravity and politeness.
Atticus: I am glad I interrupted you, since you have availed yourself
of an opportunity of giving this splendid testimonial of your judgment
respecting him; but to pursue the subject as you began.
Marcus: Let us begin, then, with praising the law itself, with those
commendations which are both deserved and appropriate to the subject.
Atticus: That is but fair, since you did the same in the case of our
ecclesiastical jurisprudence.
Marcus: You see, then, that this is the duty of magistrates, to superintend
and prescribe all things which are just and useful, and in accordance with the
law. For as the law is set over the magistrate, even so are the magistrates set
over the people. And, therefore, it may be truly said "that the magistrate
is a speaking law, and the law is a silent magistrate." Moreover, nothing
is so conformable to justice and to the condition of nature (and when I use
that expression, I wish it to be understood that I mean the law, and nothing
else) as sovereign power; without which, neither house, nor commonwealth, nor
nation, nor mankind itself, nor the entire nature of things, nor the universe
itself, could exist. For this universe is obedient to God, and land and sea are
submissive to the universe; and human life depends on the just administration
of the laws of the universe; and human life depends on the just administration
of the laws of order.
2. But to come to considerations nearer home, and more familiar to
us, all ancient nations have been at one time or other under the dominion of
kings. Which kind of authority was at first conferred on the wisest and justest
of men (and this rule mainly prevailed in our own commonwealth, as long as the
regal power lasted). Afterward, the authority of kings was handed down in
succession to their descendants, and this practice remains to this day in those
which are governed by kings. And even those to whom the regal domination was
distasteful, did not desire to be obedient to no one, but only to be always
under the authority of the same person.
For ourselves, then, as we are proposing laws for a free people, and we have
already set forth in six books all our own opinions about the best kind of
commonwealth, we shall on the present occasion endeavor to accommodate our laws
to that constitutional government of which we have expressed our approval.
It is clear, then, that magistrates are absolutely necessary; since, without
their prudence and diligence, a state cannot exist; and since it is by their
regulations that the whole commonwealth is kept within the bounds of
moderation. But it is not enough to prescribe them a rule of domination, unless
we likewise prescribe the citizens a rule of obedience. For he who commands
well, must at some time or other have obeyed; and he who obeys with modesty appears
worthy of some day or other being allowed to command. It is desirable,
therefore, that he who obeys should expect that some day he will come to
command, and that he who commands should bear in mind that ere long he may be
called to the duty of submission.
We would not, however, limit ourselves to requiring from the citizens
submission and obedience towards their magistrates; we would also enjoin them
by all means to honor and love their rulers, as Charondas prescribes in his
code. Our Plato likewise declares that they are of the race of the Titans, who,
as they rebelled against the heavenly deities, do in like manner oppose their
magistrates. These points being granted, we will, if you please, advance to the
examination of the laws themselves.
Atticus: I certainly do please, and the arrangement seems advisable.
3. Marcus: Let all authorities be just, and let them be
honestly obeyed by the people with modesty and without opposition. Let the
magistrate restrain the disobedient and mischievous citizen, by fine,
imprisonment, and corporal chastisement; unless some equal or greater power, or
the people forbid it; for there should be an appeal thereto. If the magistrate
shall have decided, and inflicted a penalty, let there be a public appeal to
the people respecting the penalty and fine imposed.
With respect to the army, and the general that commands it by martial law,
there should be no appeal from his authority. And whatever he who conducts the
war commands, shall be absolute law, and ratified as such.
As to the minor magistrates, let there be such a distribution of their legal
duties, that each may more effectively superintend his own department of
justice. In the army let those who are appointed command, and let them have
tribunes. In the city, let men be appointed as superintendents of the public
treasury. Let some devote their attention to the prison discipline, and capital
punishments. Let others supervise the public coinage of gold, and silver, and
copper. Let others judge suits and arbitrations; and let others carry the
orders of the senate into execution.
Let there likewise be aediles, curators of the city, the provisions, and the
public games, and let these offices be the first steps to higher promotions of
honor.
Let the censors take a census of the people, according to age, offspring,
family, and property. Let them have the inspection of the temples, the streets,
the aqueducts, the rates, and the customs. Let them distribute the citizens,
according to their tribes; after that let them divide them with reference to
their fortunes, ages, and ranks. Let them keep a register of the families of
those of the equestrian and plebeian orders. Let them impose a tax on
celibates. Let them guard the morals of the people. Let them permit no scandal
in the senate. Let the number of such censors be two. Let their magistracy
continue five years. Let the other magistrates be annual, but their offices
themselves should be perpetual.
Let the judge of the law who shall decide private actions, or send them for
decision to the praetor---let him be the proper guardian of civil
jurisprudence. Let him have as many colleagues of equal power, as the senate
think necessary, and the people allows him.
Let two magistrates be invested with sovereign authority; from their presiding,
judging, and counseling, let them be called praetors, judges, or consuls. Let
them have supreme authority over the army, and let them be subject to none; for
the safety of the people is the supreme law; and no one should succeed to this
magistracy till it has been held ten years---regulating the duration by an
annual law.
When a considerable war is undertaken, or discord is likely to ensue among
the citizens, let a single supreme magistrate be appointed, who shall unite in
his own person the authority of both consuls, if the senate so decrees, for six
months only. And when such a magistrate has been proclaimed under favorable
auspices, let him be the master of the people. Let him have for a colleague,
with equal powers with himself, a knight whomsoever he may choose to appoint,
as judge of the law. And when such a dictator or master of the people is
created the other magistrates shall be suppressed.
Let the auspices be observed by the senate, and let them authorize persons
of their body to elect the consuls in the Comitia, according to the
established ceremonials.
Let the commanders, generals, and lieutenants, leave the city whenever the
senate decrees or the people orders that they shall do so. Let them properly
prosecute all just wars. Let them spare our allies, and restrain themselves and
their subordinates. Let them increase the glory of our country. Let them return
home with honor. Let no one be made an ambassador with a view to his own
interest.
Let the ten officers whom the people elect to protect them against
oppression be their tribunes; and let all their prohibitions and adjudications
be established, and their persons considered inviolable, so that tribunes may
never be wanting to the people.
Let all magistrates possess their auspices and jurisdictions, and let the
senate be composed of these legitimate authorities. Let its ordinances be
absolute, and let its enactments be written and ratified, unless an equal or
greater authority disannul them. Let the order of the senators be free from reproach
and scandal, and let them be an example of virtue to all.
In the creation of magistrates, the judgment of the accused, and the
reception or rejection of laws, when suffrages are employed, let the suffrages
be at once notorious to the nobles, and free to the people.
4. If any question occur out of the established jurisdiction of the
magistrates, let another magistrate be appointed by the people, whose
jurisdiction shall expressly extend thereto. Let the consul, the praetor, the
censor, the master of the people and of the equites, and he to whom the senate
has committed the election of consuls, have full liberty to treat both with the
senate and the people, and endeavor to reconcile the interests of all parties.
Let the tribunes of the people likewise have free access to the senate, and
advocate the interests of the people in all their deliberations. Let a just
moderation predominate in the opinions and declarations of those who would thus
act as mediators between the senate and the people. Let a senator who does not
attend the senate, either show cause of his non-attendance, or submit to an
appropriate fine. Let a senator speak in his turn, with all moderation, and let
him be thoroughly acquainted with the interests of the people.
By all means avoid violence among the people. Let the greatest authority
have the greatest weight in decisions. If any one shall disturb the public
harmony, and foment party quarrels, let him be punished as a criminal. To act
the intercessor in cases of offence should be considered the part of a good
citizen. Let those who act observe the auspices; obey the public augur, and
carry into effect all proclamations, taking care that they are exhibited in the
treasury and generally known. Let the public consultations be concentrated in
one point at a time, let them instruct the people in the nature of the
question, and let all the magistrates and the people be permitted to advise on
the subject.
Let them permit no monopolies, or privileges. With respect to the capital
punishment of any citizen, let it not take place, unless by the adjudication of
the high courts of justice, and the ministry of those whom the censors have
placed over the popular orders. Let no bribes be given or received, either in
soliciting, discharging, or resigning an official situation.
If any one infringe any of these laws, let him be liable to penalty. Let
these regulations be committed to the charge of the censors. Let public
officers, on their retiring from their posts, gives the censors an account of
their conduct, but let them not by this means escape from legal prosecution if
they have been guilty of corruption.
I have here recited the whole law; now, consider the question, and give your
votes.
5. Quintus: With what conciseness, my brother, have you
brought before our eyes the duties and offices of all magistrates! But your
system of laws is almost that of our own commonwealth, although a little that
is new has also been added by you.
Marcus: Your observation is very just, my Quintus, for this is the
very system of a commonwealth which Scipio eulogizes in my treatise, and which
he mainly approves---and which cannot be kept in operation but by a successive
order of magistrates, such as we have described. For you may take it for
granted that it is the establishment of magistrates that gives its form to a
commonwealth, and it is exactly by their distribution and subordination that we
must determine the nature of the constitution. Which establishment being very
wisely and discretely settled by our ancestors, there is nothing, or at all
events very little alteration that I think necessary in the laws.
Source:
From: Oliver J. Thatcher, ed., The Library of Original Sources
(Milwaukee: University Research Extension Co., 1907), Vol. III: The Roman
World, pp. 216-241.
Scanned by: J. S. Arkenberg,
This text is part of the Internet Ancient
History Sourcebook. The Sourcebook is a collection of public domain and
copy-permitted texts related to medieval and Byzantine history.